V
Works of art are received and valued on different planes. Two polar
types stand out; with one, the accent is on the cult value; with the
other, on the exhibition value of the work. Artistic production begins
with ceremonial objects destined to serve in a cult. One may assume that
what mattered was their existence, not their being on view. The elk
portrayed by the man of the Stone Age on the walls of his cave was an
instrument of magic. He did expose it to his fellow men, but in the main
it was meant for the spirits. Today the cult value would seem to demand
that the work of art remain hidden. Certain statues of gods are
accessible only to the priest in the cella; certain Madonnas remain
covered nearly all year round; certain sculptures on medieval cathedrals
are invisible to the spectator on ground level. With the emancipation
of the various art practices from ritual go increasing opportunities for
the exhibition of their products. It is easier to exhibit a portrait
bust that can be sent here and there than to exhibit the statue of a
divinity that has its fixed place in the interior of a temple. The same
holds for the painting as against the mosaic or fresco that preceded it.
And even though the public presentability of a mass originally may have
been just as great as that of a symphony, the latter originated at the
moment when its public presentability promised to surpass that of the
mass.
With the different methods of technical reproduction of a work of art,
its fitness for exhibition increased to such an extent that the
quantitative shift between its two poles turned into a qualitative
transformation of its nature. This is comparable to the situation of the
work of art in prehistoric times when, by the absolute emphasis on its
cult value, it was, first and foremost, an instrument of magic. Only
later did it come to be recognized as a work of art. In the same way
today, by the absolute emphasis on its exhibition value the work of art
becomes a creation with entirely new functions, among which the one we
are conscious of, the artistic function, later may be recognized as
incidental. This much is certain: today photography and the film are the
most serviceable exemplifications of this new function.
....
Agamben / philosophical archaeology/ 2009
And it is something similar that Benjamin might have had in mind, when, in Overbeck’s footsteps, he wrote that in the monadological structure of the historical object are contained both ‘prehistory’ and ‘post-history’ (Vor- und Nachgeschichte), or when he suggested that the entire past must be immersed into the present in a ‘historical apocatastasis’ (Benjamin 1982, p. 573). (Apocatastasis is the restitution in the origin which, according to Origenes, takes place at the end of times; qualifying an eschatological reality as ‘historical’, Benjamin uses an image very similar to the foucaultian ‘a priori’.)
....
Agamben / philosophical archaeology/ 2009
And it is something similar that Benjamin might have had in mind, when, in Overbeck’s footsteps, he wrote that in the monadological structure of the historical object are contained both ‘prehistory’ and ‘post-history’ (Vor- und Nachgeschichte), or when he suggested that the entire past must be immersed into the present in a ‘historical apocatastasis’ (Benjamin 1982, p. 573). (Apocatastasis is the restitution in the origin which, according to Origenes, takes place at the end of times; qualifying an eschatological reality as ‘historical’, Benjamin uses an image very similar to the foucaultian ‘a priori’.)
No comments:
Post a Comment